From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Incomplete information)
In economics
and game
theory, complete information is an economic situation or game in
which knowledge about other market participants or players is available to all
participants. The utility functions (including risk aversion), payoffs,
strategies and "types" of players are thus common knowledge.
Inversely,
in a game with incomplete information, players do not possess full
information about their opponents. Some players possess private information, a
fact that the others should take into account when forming expectations about
how those players will behave. A typical example is an auction: each player
knows his own utility function (valuation for the item), but does not know the
utility function of the other players. See [1]
for more examples.
Games of
incomplete information arise frequently in social science. For instance, John
Harsanyi was motivated by consideration of arms control negotiations, where the
players may be uncertain both of the capabilities of their opponents and of
their desires and beliefs.
It is often
assumed that the players have some statistical information about the other
players. E.g., in an auction, each player knows that the valuations of the
other players are drawn from some probability distribution. In this case, the
game is called a Bayesian game.
Complete vs.
perfect information
Complete
information is importantly different from perfect information. In a game of
complete information, the structure of the game and the payoff functions of the
players are commonly known but players may not see all of the moves made by
other players (for instance, the initial placement of ships in Battleship);
there may also be a chance element (as in most card games). Conversely, in
games of perfect information, every player observes other players' moves, but
may lack some information on others' payoffs, or on the structure of the game.
A game with complete information may or may not have perfect information, and
vice versa.
- Examples of games with imperfect but complete information are card games, where each player's cards are hidden from other players but objectives are known, as in contract bridge and poker, if the outcomes are assumed to be binary (players can only win or lose). However, in practice, most games have slightly incomplete information because of non-binary outcomes (e.g., some people may value getting the second or third place, while some only care about the first place), making it impossible to know the exact form of the objective function the other players are trying to maximize and thus the way they will respond to different situations.]
- Examples of games with incomplete but perfect information are conceptually more difficult to imagine. Suppose you are playing a game of chess against an opponent who will be paid some substantial amount of money if a particular event happens (an arrangement of pieces, for instance), but you do not know what the event is. In this case you have perfect information, since you know what each move of the opponent is. However, since you do not know the payoff function of the other player (which will affect its behavior even if it does not alter your own victory conditions), it is a game of incomplete information.
Games of
incomplete information can be converted into games of complete but imperfect
information under the "common prior assumption." This assumption is
commonly made for pragmatic reasons, but its justification remains
controversial among economists.
See also
References
- ^ Levin, Jonathan (2002). "Games with Incomplete Information" (PDF). Retrieved 25 August 2016.
- ^ Osborne, M. J.; Rubinstein, A. (1994). "Chapter 6: Extensive Games with Perfect Information". A Course in Game Theory. Cambridge M.A.: The MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-65040-1.
- ^ Thomas, L. C. (2003). Games, Theory and Applications. Mineola N.Y.: Dover Publications. p. 19. ISBN 0-486-43237-8.
- ^ Osborne, M. J.; Rubinstein, A. (1994). "Chapter 11: Extensive Games with Imperfect Information". A Course in Game Theory. Cambridge M.A.: The MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-65040-1.
- Fudenberg, D. and Tirole, J. (1993) Game Theory. MIT Press. (see Chapter 6, sect 1)
- Gibbons, R. (1992) A primer in game theory. Harvester-Wheatsheaf. (see Chapter 3)
- Ian Frank, David Basin (1997), Artificial Intelligence 100 (1998) 87-123. "Search in games with incomplete information: a case study using Bridge card play".
No comments:
Post a Comment